Back to the Future: Habermas's the Future of Human Nature (Critical Essay) (Letter to the Editor) Back to the Future: Habermas's the Future of Human Nature (Critical Essay) (Letter to the Editor)

Back to the Future: Habermas's the Future of Human Nature (Critical Essay) (Letter to the Editor‪)‬

The Hastings Center Report 2007, March-April, 37, 2

    • 2,99 €
    • 2,99 €

Description de l’éditeur

To the Editor: I have already had my say in these pages on Habermas on bioethics, and it is bad form for an author to cite himself. Forgive me, then, for protesting that Elizabeth Fenton's "Liberal Eugenics and Human Nature: Against Habermas" (Nov-Dec 2006) disappoints me, and not only because she does not gratify my ego or satisfy my sense of justice by engaging the arguments in my own paper (see "Rethinking 'Liberal Eugenics': Reflections and Questions on Habermas on Bioethics," Nov-Dec 2005, and the letters in Mar-Apr 2006). The principal source of my disappointment is that, though Fenton accurately tells us what Habermas claims in his book, The Future of Human Nature (Polity Press, 2003), she fails to come to terms with why. To give some substance to this charge: First, Fenton calls "overblown" Habermas's worry that liberal eugenics might distort human relationships, especially the parent-child relationship. Why? Against Habermas, Fenton notes that "the parent-child relationship is inherently one of inequality; even without explicitly choosing a child's characteristics or traits, a parent has considerable control over the development of that child." Now, yes, a parent does have "considerable control"; but any reflective parent would acknowledge--and all parents should acknowledge--that there are also "considerable" limits to parental power, both in fact and in principle. In fact, socialization is a clumsy and imprecise tool: parents wield it, but often they know not how and to what effect. Habermas asks us to consider a question of principle: whether exercising control over a child's genetic makeup--and so presumably going beyond the most controlling parents we have known to date--would be going too far. Habermas also gives us reasons for thinking that genetically engineering our children would be both unprecedented and imprudent--reasons focusing in particular on how the child's relation to her body might be affected. Following Habermas, I discuss these reasons at length in my paper; Fenton ignores our "bodiliness" altogether. Instead she observes that "such inequalities or asymmetries abound within the human moral community," and that "humans have found ways to overcome them," for example, "by defining universal human rights." But the invocation of "universal human rights" is beside the point. The question is not whether a genetically engineered child would have rights--of course she would--but whether she might feel prevented from freely exercising them. There is much to say here, and it is not at all obvious how to answer; but Fenton does not even speak to the question!

GENRE
Science et nature
SORTIE
2007
1 mars
LANGUE
EN
Anglais
LONGUEUR
8
Pages
ÉDITIONS
Hastings Center
TAILLE
167,3
Ko

Plus de livres par The Hastings Center Report

Is Marketing the Enemy of Pharmaceutical Innovation?(Essays) Is Marketing the Enemy of Pharmaceutical Innovation?(Essays)
2009
Rx for the Pharmaceutical Industry: Call Your Doctors (Essays) (Viewpoint Essay) Rx for the Pharmaceutical Industry: Call Your Doctors (Essays) (Viewpoint Essay)
2009
Medicine's Duty to Treat Pandemic Illness: Solidarity and Vulnerability: Most Accounts of Why Physicians Have a Duty to Treat Patients During a Pandemic Look to the Special Ethical Standards of the Medical Profession. An Adequate Account Must Be Deeper and Broader: It Must Set the Professional Duty Alongside Other Individual Commitments and Broader Social Values. Medicine's Duty to Treat Pandemic Illness: Solidarity and Vulnerability: Most Accounts of Why Physicians Have a Duty to Treat Patients During a Pandemic Look to the Special Ethical Standards of the Medical Profession. An Adequate Account Must Be Deeper and Broader: It Must Set the Professional Duty Alongside Other Individual Commitments and Broader Social Values.
2009
Clinical Ethics Consulting and Conflict of Interest: Structurally Intertwined: Clinical Ethical Consultants are Subject to an Unavoidable Conflict of Interest. Their Work Requires That They be Independent, But Incentives Attached to Their Role Chip Relentlessly at Independence. This is a Problem Without Any Solution, But It can at Least be Ameliorated Through Careful Management. Clinical Ethics Consulting and Conflict of Interest: Structurally Intertwined: Clinical Ethical Consultants are Subject to an Unavoidable Conflict of Interest. Their Work Requires That They be Independent, But Incentives Attached to Their Role Chip Relentlessly at Independence. This is a Problem Without Any Solution, But It can at Least be Ameliorated Through Careful Management.
2007
Are Alcoholics Less Deserving of Liver Transplants? when Does Behavior Trigger a Lesser Claim to Medical Resources? when Does Chronic Drinking, For Example, Mean That One has a Lesser Claim to a Liver Transplant? Only when One's Behavior Becomes a Callous Indifference to Others' Needs--when One Knows the Consequences of Heavy Drinking and Knows That by Drinking One May End up Depriving Someone else of a Liver. Are Alcoholics Less Deserving of Liver Transplants? when Does Behavior Trigger a Lesser Claim to Medical Resources? when Does Chronic Drinking, For Example, Mean That One has a Lesser Claim to a Liver Transplant? Only when One's Behavior Becomes a Callous Indifference to Others' Needs--when One Knows the Consequences of Heavy Drinking and Knows That by Drinking One May End up Depriving Someone else of a Liver.
2007
Will New Ways of Creating Stem Cells Dodge the Objections? Will New Ways of Creating Stem Cells Dodge the Objections?
2005